Judged by the timeliness of
my posts this hardly even counts as a blog. On the other hand, if something is
not worth talking about two months after it was current it was probably never
worth talking about in the first place. With that in mind, I turn to Gay
Talese's provocative article in the April 11 New Yorker entitled
"The Voyeur's Motel".
Talese describes a
relationship he developed with a man in Colorado whose voyeuristic inclinations
were so overpowering that he went to the length of buying a motel and
outfitting the ceilings of the guest rooms with customized gratings that
allowed him, from an attic runway constructed with equal care, to view his
guests in their bedrooms and bathrooms without their knowledge. It is not the
first time we have heard this sort of thing - I recall a guy who was eventually
caught after installing two-way mirrors in his guest rooms - but Talese's
subject, by the name of Gerald Foos, adds some interesting twists.
Probably the most shocking
is that his first and second wives were complicit in his activities,
though neither one had more than a passing interest if any in voyeurism
herself; indeed, the first wife helped him by acting as a subject and assistant
to ensure both accurate placement of the gratings and his careful concealment
behind them. Both apparently had sex with him regularly, unperturbed by his obsessive
voyeurism. Another twist is that he not only kept this habit up for 15 years, but
took copious notes, including what one might generously call philosophical, or
at least sociological, reflections on what he was observing. (It sounds like
masturbation was the first order of priority, though, with the notes
"reflected in tranquility", if I may.) And the last is that he
reached out to Talese and invited him out to the motel, shared his activities
with him, sent him copies of what he had written and finally released him from
any obligation to keep it private - brave stuff for a guy who spied on his
paying guests for a decade and a half.
I have no intention of
repeating the rest of the details here; by all means read the New
Yorker piece, or Talese's new book from which it is excerpted, if you are interested (curious, excited, disgusted,
outraged...) Quite a few people have commented on the ethics of Talese's lengthy relationship with Foos and his decision not to expose him to the police. That's all fair game but not my concern here. What I want to discuss is what Talese makes of all this, and what
he doesn't. In the article, at least, it seems
to me that he makes some great observations but avoids judgment on the deepest moral issues
of the situation.
He does hit the
psychological nail on the head a couple of times. One is the following general
characterization of voyeurism: "A voyeur is motivated by anticipation; he
invests endless hours in the hope of seeing what he wishes to see. Yet for
every erotic episode he witnesses he is also privy to hundreds of mundane
moments representing the ordinary daily routines..." Anyone who has been in
a situation where there was an expectation of some discreet, sexually
titillating experience of neighborly nudity, knows that this is exactly how it
is: you wait, and wait, maybe staring at a dark window hoping a light will come
on, or a lighted window hoping your subject will enter the frame, and if they
do, you then wait, and wait, and wait as they do stuff around the house,
entertain guests, or whatever, until something either happens, perhaps so
quickly that you can rub your blurry eyes and miss it, or the light goes out and you
just completely wasted a good chunk of time.
Talese captures this
feeling so well you can't help but wonder if learning about it really required
studying Gerald Foos. Most guys have been there, by pressure if not by choice.
Early in my first semester at college (I was 16 at the time) some guy talk over
dinner turned to the matter of a very impressive young woman on the female side
of the dormitory, and one of the group announced that she regularly disrobed
with her curtains open right across the courtyard from his window, where he and
his friends took in the show. Several of us were invited to participate in the
viewing that evening. Unfortunately or not, depending on which side of the
window you were on, no such performance took place on that occasion.
Most men don't seek this
stuff out in the obsessive manner of Gerald Foos, or buy a telescope like
Dudley Moore in 10 - but then again, I knew a fellow, a co-worker at my first computer programming job, whose window faced the monumental apartment buildings
across the Hudson in Jersey City, and who not only told me that he bought an excellent
telescope for exactly this reason, but assured me that his attractive Filipino
wife tolerated and occasionally participated in his astronomical
pursuits. In any case, there are few innocents at this sport among men who have
lived in an urban or college environment, and anyone who has allowed himself
(or herself) to get particularly entranced with a certain subject can surely
attest that there is no greater threat to human accomplishment than the time
wasted waiting for some skin or lingerie to be revealed. One can only imagine
what it must have been like for Foos, hour after dusty hour up in the attic,
day in day out, hoping that some woman or couple, preferably not too unattractive,
would put on a show, above the sheets, with the lights on. Adding up all the
juicy moments he did observe might sound like grounds for some perverse
jealousy, until you divide it into the hours he spent waiting, or the number of
disappointments, which should have us thanking our lucky stars that we never
found a motel to buy.
The other great observation
Talese makes follows from this. He says of Foos's journal, "The more I
read, the more convinced I became that Foos's stilted metaphysics were his way
of attempting to elevate his disturbing pastime into something of value."
That says a lot more than might appear at first glance. The voyeur is torn by
two passions: the desire to make something of himself, and the obsession with
watching others. In fact they are more or less the same thing: the creative
impulse is there in the naughty act of getting some kind of sensual
gratification with minimal effort, a vicarious sex act without all the
preliminary engagement that having sex usually involves. The voyeur locates
himself outside the social world, looking at it, judging it, using it, and that
impulse could equally be the pose of an artist or writer. In fact that is
precisely what an artist is, a voyeur of other lives, only not of a strictly
sexual sort. The voyeur's entire creative impulse has been hijacked by one of
its components, the sexual one, and he struggles with that and tries to do what
he can to even it out. Foos is brilliant in a slightly cockamamie way, for he has managed
to close the gap - by his own less than perfect logic - between the
time-wasting, energy-sapping, often demoralizing pursuit that he is literally
addicted to, and the true Foos that he believes is inside: the astute observer
of humanity, the writer with original thoughts on the human condition.
By my lights, Talese gets
high marks for these insights. Foos, too, gets high marks, in a way, for the
occasional honest reflections that Talese reports him making. After numerous
clandestine observations of dishonest and degrading activity by his guests he
begins to refer to himself as a "futilitarian" - the word put me in
mind of the aesthetics of Stanley Kubrick rather than British moral theory,
not because Kubrick once famously depicted a deranged hotel manager, but
because in film after film he offers glimpses of a human psyche that mounts a
tremendous, but ultimately futile struggle against its own fatal flaws.
Elsewhere Talese quotes Foos referring to voyeurs as "cripples" who
are "flawed and imperfect" (as writers too, apparently). Foos may be
slimy but he is neither stupid nor entirely deluded about himself, and that is
part of what makes him an object of interest for Talese, and for us.
But apart from the interesting psychology and neo-Victorian
titillation of the story there are moral issues that Talese is somewhat
reserved about confronting. Foos makes it clear that he does not think his
spying is morally depraved, and he has arguments to back this up. The arguments
are essentially: (1) nobody can be considered harmed if they never know they
are harmed; (2) there is no other way to acquire untarnished sociological data
on human nature and sexuality, for letting your subjects know they are subjects
would alter their behavior, and the purer data is valuable in itself; and (3)
given the extent of government and corporate surveillance in society today,
there is no one with the moral authority to criticize his extremely limited and
petty form of surveillance. I have reformulated these theses a bit, but I
believe they represent the key points of Foos's defense of his behavior as
reported by Talese. There are also strong suggestions that Foos thinks most
people are bigger slimebuckets than he is and don't deserve his respect, but
this is an indefensible general judgment and not really a claim worth
considering.
What to make of these
claims? Talese does not really engage with them, at least not by way of
assessing their value as arguments; but they point in the direction of fairly
fundamental moral issues. Let's take them one at a time.
The easiest to deal with, I
think, is the second point. There are ethical standards for conducting
scientific research, and to accept Foos's view would mean jettisoning some of
them wholesale. That in itself doesn't prove anything, but the consequences can
be ramified. The suggestion is that it is okay to conduct research on human
subjects without their knowledge or consent if it is the best way to do it and
may have benefits. Suppose we want to test a new drug that we know has a
negligible effect on the vast majority of people - let's say it turns one hair
on their heads a slightly lighter shade of their actual hair color - but where
that effect can give us important information about its use in curing an
insidious disease. Let's also say that people who know they are being given the
drug immediately develop resistance to it. May we dose some unaware members of
the population at large with the drug? It seems obvious that we are not allowed
to do that, for many different reasons. One is that we can't be sure that there
won't be a few people who have severe allergic reactions to the drug; just as
Foos can't guarantee that he won't slip, causing one of his guests to become
aware that they have been viewed, whereupon they might suffer severe
psychological harm at this knowledge. There is virtually no personally invasive
act that can be guaranteed never to have consequences, so we cannot utilize
subjects in this way even if we intend to cause them no harm. Kant says that we
cannot use people as means to our ends no matter how great the benefits, for to
do so is to devalue one of the things that defines them as human beings: their
ability to exercise free will. That is a thought worth pondering whenever one
is tempted to minimize the damage done to others by using them in ways they
would not choose to be used.
This point has some
relevance to a broader debate in another context: the use of aggregate Internet
usage data for commercial or security purposes without the consent of those
whose actions are being accumulated. Even if individuals cannot be identified
from the data, there is no getting around the fact that it is specific actions
we have taken, many of which we would not choose to share if asked, that are
the source of the aggregate facts. There is something very disturbing about
knowing that someone - via some software robot - is gathering information on
your buying habits, Google searches, Facebook posts and the like, and either
selling it to others for marketing purposes or mining its security value. We
want to have a say even in this remote and apparently harmless practice because
it just seems wrong that anyone can track the actions of ordinary people and
use the results for their own purposes. We want to be the judges of
whether our actions should be collected, categorized and cross-referenced, not
Google and certainly not the likes of Gerald Foos.
So I think the research
excuse goes out the door pretty swiftly. What about the surveillance
argument? If everyone does it, who is going to throw the first stone? Well, I
have just more or less committed myself to the idea that Foos's
"research" is on the same unsound moral ground as Internet
surveillance, so clearly I think there is a relationship there. But what of the
fact that civil society permits this surveillance to go on, and the government
and private entities actually do it, so no one has the moral standing to call
what Foos was doing "wrong"? This point is valid, but it doesn't make
his activities any better, it simply means that we have failed to correct the
larger social problem. Ask yourself: would we consider the government better or
worse if it simply threw up its hands and overlooked invasions of privacy in
every form after recognizing its own transgressions? The answer is obvious, and
points to a fact that the clever but not bright Foos overlooks: that he is a
kind of predator, and we always want to be protected from predators, regardless
of what other faults there may be with the executive function of government.
This point stands even if
we make more allowance than we probably should for Foos's alleged
"research". Let's say his research amounts to something of value;
that doesn't change the predatory nature of his behavior. Keep in mind that
jerking off came first - he even claimed to have sex with his wife in his attic
perch, turned on I guess by what he had seen that night. One seriously doubts
that he would have created this attic of iniquity if he had for some reason
been unable to receive sexual gratification and only conduct his putative
sociological observations. Voyeurs do not deserve to be categorized with
rapists, child molesters or other sexual offenders who directly take hold of
the bodies of their victims, but they are predators of a sort, who know they
are (often, at least) taking advantage of subjects in a way they would not
consent to. Back to Kant, someone I suspect Foos never read (or at least understood).
That leaves the victimless
crime argument. Here we get into some nasty tangles. Can someone be called a
victim if they never know they are a victim? Can someone be said to have been
"harmed" if they did not suffer in any way whatsoever? Let's say
someone breaks into your house while you are gone, but does it so carefully
that they leave no trace, take nothing from you, and leave before you get back.
Can we say they harmed you? Assume you live in remote woods where there are no
neighbors to see these breakins. Now let's say they happen every day of your
life and you never notice a single thing - have you been harmed?
This is a little like such
"metaphysical" questions as "If a tree falls in the woods and no
one hears it does it make a noise?" and "Isn't it possible that the
universe disappears for a split second while you are asleep and comes back
exactly as it was?" It's the knowledge issue: to what extent does our
judgment of what is depend on our understanding of what we can know?
Aristotle asked if it was possible to harm the dead. Most people don't worry
about such things, but Gerald Foos and his ilk force us to consider these sorts of
questions.
I will admit that my
response to this argument is somewhat colored by my response to another issue
of sexual ethics, specifically the issue of child pornography. As disgusted as
I am that it even exists, I do not feel that viewing it should be a
crime, nor even downloading it or possessing it except with intent to sell or
distribute it. I have a serious problem with the notion that the mere exercise
of one's sense faculties should be a crime under virtually any circumstances.
You can perhaps point to viewing classified information as a counterexample,
but once I again I would say, if the person has done nothing to facilitate or
abet the release of such information, but just, for instance, went to some
ordinary location where they had heard that such information would be
available, they are guilty of no morally reprehensible act. People who create or in any way
abet the creation or distribution of child pornography should face severe
penalties, but people who do nothing but view it - especially online, where the
practical obstacles to receiving it may be minimal - should at worst be
referred for counseling.
The question for me is,
what is Gerald Foos guilty of other than observing what was readily available
to his senses? Certainly he was not merely opening his eyes, and allowing them
to remain open as a person disrobed in his visual field. Foos created these
opportunities, but what does that mean, exactly? If I happen to know that a
woman regularly disrobes in front of a remote open window that is viewable from
a certain angle, and I place myself there at the right time to catch a view of
her, I am also creating an opportunity. What have I done wrong, exactly? Here
you could say that I took advantage of the trust, built into our every day
lives, that people will not go out of their way to create opportunities that
involve utilizing us for their own ends. The situation is perhaps something
like stealing someone's identity for a purpose that does not directly harm them
financially, but entangles their personhood in something they would most likely
not do if asked. Now what about Foos? He went well beyond standing in front of
a window. Actually he apparently started out doing just that. (You can read the
lurid details in Talese's article.) But how does his motel operation differ
from that?
As I see it, the motel
operation involves a similar kind of betrayal of unspoken trust, but also
something even more objectionable: it involves an intent to deceive. Foos
carefully constructed his viewing opportunities in such a way as to ensure that
the grating in the ceiling would deceive his guests into assuming that they
were simply air control ducts. He adjusted them to hide his presence, and
designed the attic to keep his activities secret, all the while expecting
guests to walk innocently into his lair. In handing them the keys to their
rooms he conveyed an unwritten code that they would experience a certain level
of privacy common to such situations, all the while knowing that they would be
maximally exposed.
This is a little like handing in a plagiarized term paper
or dissertation: you actively take advantage of the code of trust (which may or may not be explicit) that
this is your own work in order to get something that the other person in the
transaction would not otherwise give you. It is also a bit like undisclosed
corporate surveillance of office workers - keystroke counters, hidden
cameras and the like. But it is not like federal surveillance of
suspects for whom we have strong evidence that they may be committing crimes.
This is a mistake Foos makes, perhaps a result of his experiences seeing or
hearing guests do things that might throw questions on their own integrity.
There may be no angels among us, but it is a fundamental tenet of a democratic
society that no one can be subjected to such invasions of privacy on the basis
of something like Foos's "futilitarianism". Even disregarding legal
restrictions on warrants and the like, without a reason to believe that a
particular individual is violating your trust you have no legitimate reason to
invade their privacy.
Foos betrayed and deceived
his guests, violating the norms of society that operate in these situations,
but did not refrain from charging them a fee for providing him with an
opportunity to fulfill his urges and fantasies. In the big picture, they paid
him for the possibility of maintaining the palace of perversion in which they
were abused. What he should have done is open a motel for exhibitionists and
announce to them at the outset that they would be watched, perhaps receiving
some money from those who sought out such situations and offering a reasonable
sum to those who might otherwise be reluctant. This might not have made him enough
money to maintain the operation, but that's life.
So I have answered the
third question indirectly, because I think we have to accept the idea that the
notion of "harm" should be restricted to injuries that have a
material effect on us, which usually means we have to be aware of them directly
or indirectly, immediately or in the future. That is not the case when someone
is merely watched, without further consequences. But betrayal is not limited to
"harm" and carries its own moral weight. No one can be called
innocent for having an affair that their spouse never finds out about, at least
if the spouse would feel betrayed had it become known to them. Thus there are
moral standards where the bar is lower than that of causing "harm".
And in most of those cases, we as a society know what Foos's subjects may not
personally know: that if we let things like this go by, we are all in danger of
become the sorts of victims that Foos's guests became.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment